Consciousness and the Symbolic Universe
Although a developed
aesthetic sense and good manipulative skills are necessary for the production
of art, they are not sufficient in and of themselves. What sets true artistic
expression apart from the behavior of an animal, such as a bowerbird that
decorates its’ nest in order to attract a mate, is that artistic expression
requires higher-order consciousness. Higher-order consciousness means that the
artist is not only aware of aesthetic differences, but they are also aware of
their own awareness and hence the possibility that others share this awareness
or experiential world. One way to get a handle on the evolution of higher-order
consciousness is through a phylogenetic comparison.
The German scientist, Jacob
Von Uexkull, used the term Umwelt to
describe the perceptional world that is experienced by different species. The
perceptual world of a bloodhound for example, would be much more dominated by
information relating to olfaction than information from other sensory
modalities including vision. Uexkull believed that as organisms evolved more
sense organs and greater neurological complexity, their overall awareness
increased. Thus, the Umwelt of an
earthworm would be of a very rudimentary nature consisting of simple somatosensory
information. Just increasing the number of sense organs necessitated an
increase in neurological complexity to some degree. However, once the senses
that we are familiar with had evolved in vertebrates, there was a great deal of
brain evolution still to take place. A system of cross-referencing across the
different sense modalities was a critical aspect of this neurological
evolution. For example, the sound of a snapping twig could be localized for
visual scanning and then the olfactory senses could be brought to bear to
determine if indeed an intruder was in the general vicinity. There is evidence
that certain cross-modal associations have become hardwired possibly to improve
perceptual efficiency and to lower response times. English children were
compared to children from Kenya in a task that required them to match a
nonsense word with a pictoral display (Davis, 1961). Children from both groups
matched the word “malume” with a curved shape and the word “takete” with a
pointed shape.
As was pointed out in the
chapters on brain development and language, the exigencies of functioning in a
social environment greatly accelerated brain evolution and consequently the
general level of consciousness or awareness. It was speculated that the
development of a theory of mind, i.e., possessing the idea that others have a
mind similar to one’s own and using this concept to try to manipulate the
behavior of the others, was a key factor in the evolution of higher primates.
Unfortunately, it has been difficult to demonstrate the existence of theory of
mind in non-human primate species to date. If theory of mind exists in other
primate species, it may be in an incipient form, which is to say it may be a
completely non-conscious process. Since theory of mind is currently
conceptualized as being a fully conscious process, we may need another term to
describe what various species of monkeys and apes are actually doing when they
try to manipulate the behavior of others.
The first requisite in
having a bonafide theory of mind, i.e., a conscious theory of mind, is
self-awareness. By self-awareness we mean that an individual has a mental
construct of oneself as a distinct entity, separate from everyone and
everything else. In 1970, Gordon Gallup reported an experiment which he claimed
to demonstrate self-awareness in chimpanzees. His experiment was a variation of
the rouge test, which had been used by developmental psychologists for many
years to demonstrate the point in human development when very young children
first demonstrate self-awareness. In the developmental test, a mark of rouge,
or some other distinctive coloring, is clandestinely placed on the forehead of
the young child. The child is then placed in front of a mirror. Very young
children, around one year in age, will typically look at the mirror image and
react to it as if they were looking at another child. They will attempt to play
with this other child they see in the mirror. Most human children around 18
months of age show a different response. They look in the mirror, note there is
a mark of coloring upon their foreheads, and then they try to wipe it away.
This response is seen as being indicative of a concept of self. More
conservative critics say it does not really demonstrate self-concept but only
mirror recognition, which may be a different quality.
Gallop (1970) used this same
procedure when a chimpanzee was anesthetized for its’ periodical medical
checkup; an odorless red dye was applied to the chimps forehead while it lay
unconscious. When the animal regained consciousness a mirror was placed next to
its’ cage, and the chimpanzee showed all the behaviors indicative of mirror
self-recognition. The animal tried to wipe the dye from its’ forehead and it
also positioned its’ body at various angles in front of the mirror in order to
see places it could not ordinarily see on its’ own body. Since Gallop’s early
experiment, numerous other chimpanzees have passed the mirror test as well as
other species of great apes including the orangutan and some gorillas that had
been reared by humans (Gallup & Suarez, 1986; Patterson, & Cohn, 1994; Patterson, 1984; Povinelli, 1993).
Because of the inherent adaptive differences in intelligent marine species such
as the bottlenose dolphin, procedures used to demonstrate self-awareness in
primates are highly problematic with cetacean species (Marino, Reiss & Gallup, 1994). Nevertheless, studies using
mirrors and TV monitors in mirror mode make a compelling case for the existence
of self-recognition in the bottlenose dolphin (Marten & Psarakos, 1994). Not all great apes immediately pass
the mirror test and often they require prolonged exposure to mirrors before
they understand what they are looking at. However, regardless of the length of
time that the individuals are exposed to mirrors, no member of any other
species, outside of the humans, great apes, and possibly bottlenose dolphins
have ever passed this mirror recognition test (Gallup, 1994). Monkeys can be in
the presence of a mirror for thousand of hours without ever acquiring this
level of awareness (Gallup, 1977). At first they react to it as an intruding
member of their own species, but eventually they habituate and ignore the
mirror all together. Based on these findings, it would seem that the best place
to look for theory of mind in non-human species would be in our close relatives
the chimpanzees.
In 1978, David Premack and
Guy Woodruff reported the results of a study on an adult chimpanzee named
Sarah. The investigators showed Sarah a series of videotapes with human actors portraying
various problems. For example, the videotape might show a human actor jumping
up and down trying to reach a bunch of bananas hanging from the ceiling that
were just out of reach. Following this videotape, Sarah would be given a set of
photographs, one of which showed a solution to the problem, in this case,
several boxes stacked on top of each other just below the bunch of bananas.
Sarah would consistently choose the photograph that represented a viable
solution to the problem shown in the videotape. Interestingly, Sarah’s was much
more likely to choose a “good”, i.e., correct, outcome if the actor in the
videotape was a trainer that she liked. If the videotape depicted an individual
whom Sarah was suspected of disliking she would typically choose an outcome
that displayed the actor in some mishap such as lying under cement blocks.
Based on these findings, the investigators concluded that Sarah recognized the
videotape as representing a problem, understood the actor’s purpose, and chose
solutions compatible with that purpose except in those instances that involved
a particular individual that she disliked. This, Premack and Woodrup argued,
demonstrated theory of mind in chimpanzees. Unfortunately, additional,
corroborating evidence for theory of mind in chimpanzees has not been
forthcoming.
David Povinelli has worked
extensively on the problem of demonstrating theory of mind in chimpanzees but
generally his results have been nil (Povinelli and Preuss, 1995). Although he
has time and time again confirmed Gallop’s original findings of self-awareness,
or at least mirror self-recognition in chimpanzees (Povinelli, Gallup, Eddy,
& Bierschwale, 1997) the outcomes of the theory of mind studies have not
corroborated Premack’s earlier (1978) findings. Povinelli and Eddy (1996)
investigated theory of mind in chimpanzees by having their chimp subjects
observe two human trainers who were present when food was cashed in a certain
secret location. The chimps could see the trainers but not the location of the
food. In one human trainer, the cloth covered the eyes like a blindfold, while
in the other, the cloth was placed lower on the face acting as a gag. All of
the chimpanzees tested showed no discrimination between the two trainers and
were just as likely to beg for food from the blindfolded individual, who had no
knowledge of the food’s location, as from the sighted individual. On the other
hand, human children as young as two years of age easily discriminated between
the two experimenters and preferentially choose the experimenter whose vision
was unimpeded for the reinforcer, in this case, stickers.
By age four, the theory of
mind concept is well developed in human children. For example, a child is given
a crayon box only to find the box is full of candles instead of crayons. When
the experimenter asks the child what another child would expect to find in the
same box, a child who is over four years of age will answer “crayons,” and a
younger child, will answer “candles.” Based on these findings, it is assumed children
under four years of age do not have a fully developed theory of mind concept.
Autistic individuals typically fail this sort of false belief test and an
absence of theory of mind has been proposed to explain many of the symptoms of
autism.
Autism is characterized by
extreme deficits in social behavior and understanding. Children with autism
display an emotional indifference to others and treat close family members
exactly the same way they treat complete strangers. Verbal and non-verbal
communication is extremely impaired. These individuals also display no
imagination or creativity. They prefer a sameness of routine and are very
disturbed by any slight changes. Autistic individuals interpret speech very
literally, for example, if one asks “Can you pass the salt?” a child with
autism might reply “Yes” as though they were being queried about their ability
to do this rather than being requested to actually pass the salt to the
individual (Mitchell, 1997). Certain high-functioning autistic individuals show
great abilities in making mathematical calculations or in memorizing a great
amount of seemingly irrelevant information, such as the contents of phone
books. There is a very mechanical, machine-like quality in these abilities. For
example, two young autistic artists, Steven Wiltshire and Nadia, produce
extremely realistic and detailed line drawings. These drawing have an extreme
photographic quality about them, as if they were produced by a camera rather
than a thinking, feeling being. Many of these deficits seem to be directly
linked to a lack of theory of mind in autistic individuals. A failure to
understand other peoples beliefs would restrict a child to excessive literal
interpretations of the speech of others. Their problems of relating socially to
others and understanding the emotions of others could also be directly linked
to their failure to understand theory of mind.
Although some of the symptoms of autism can be directly causally linked to a poorly developed theory of mind, it is probably more accurate to view the deficits in theory of mind and the other deficits as part of a global impairment. These global deficits are due to neurological abnormalities, particularly in a region of the brain known as the cerebellum. As was pointed out in chapter 2, the cerebellum is involved in the precise sequencing of motor movements, particularly ballistic movements. This was the basis of Calvin’s so-called, ballistic hypothesis, namely that the development of the cerebellum due to the selection for more accurate throwing movements provided the requisite neurological substrates for language evolution. The cerebellar abnormalities that result in autism suggest the cerebellum plays a critical role, not only in ballistic motor sequencing, but also in the sequencing of language, social intelligence, imagination and creativity, theory of mind and intentionally. It would seem that there has been a long history of co-evolutionary development between all of these traits.
The efforts of a few
autistic artists not withstanding, the key features of the creativity that have
characterized our species since the late Pleistocene are higher order consciousness, theory of mind, and intentionally.
A developed aesthetic sense and symbolic reasoning are, of course, also
necessary elements in producing art but they are not sufficient in and of
themselves. As we have seen, an aesthetic sense evolves directly from adaptive
preferences, which are exhibited in other animal species. Our phylogenetic
cousins, the great apes, are quite adept at manipulating and understanding
symbols and although there are examples of chimpanzee paintings, such endeavors
are not a part of the normal repertoire of the species. Only in our species is
a effort made to creatively manipulate elements of the outer world such that
they can express something of our inner subjective state as individuals, or
collectively, as groups of individuals.
As we noted earlier, there
is an intimate link between art and play and ritual. These elements of art and
play and ritual come full circle when we ritualize play into athletic
competitions and these competitions are appreciated as expressions of art in a
very real sense. When a football fan delights in watching a receiver stretch
out to catch a pass over the middle before being pummeled violently by a pair
of linebackers, this is just as much a form of artistic appreciation as that
experienced by thousands of painting enthusiasts who visit the Louvre each day
in Paris. The essence of art is its ability to captivate. Modern sports do just
that by displaying grace and elegance often juxtaposed with violence. The
innate preferences that maintain the complex cultural traditions that manifest
as sporting events probably arose through the adaptive advantage accrued from
having a very active interest in intertribal skirmishes. The central function
of sporting contests, in terms of evolved adaptations, is not to produce
aesthetic responses but these responses are certainly a common phenomenon.
The same is true of
entertainment. Despite the label of “entertainment arts” the primary function
of entertainment is not to produce art, although this is often an outcome
incidental and sometimes integral to the production of entertainment.
Entertainment taps into our innate interest in the social behavior of our
fellow humans. In particular, we are interested in sex, courtship, competition,
and danger. Narrative, the telling of stories, is probably as old as language
itself. A keen interest in attending to stories would have been essential for
assimilating the cultural database. A powerful adaptive advantage would belong
to individuals possessing such an interest in narrative, while, conversely,
individuals who lacked such an interest would have been at severe disadvantage.
The existence of thousands of myths, legends, folk-tales, novels, plays, and
movies is the result of our having descended from ancestors who had a definite
preference for attending to stories. As to what percentage of “entertainment”
represents art is open to debate. If we use Dissanayake's definition of art, as
something made special, then the sheer banality of most works of entertainment
excludes them from the category, art.
Art enriches virtually every aspect of human existence. It can exist as something in and of itself. More often it is embedded in other features of human life. Entertainment, religion, body adornment, architecture, transportation, play, are all enhanced by art. Even science is enhanced by elegant creativity. Art is made possible by a combination of inner aesthetic values (a feature we share with other species) and higher order consciousness (a feature known to exist only in humans) that gives us the capacity to act intentionally. The highly developed human brain is capable of generating complex mental representations including elaborate visual images. Higher order consciousness gives us the capacity to be aware of our own mental representations and also, to be aware that consciousness and mental attributes can exist in others. This provides the impetus to shape matter in such a way that it can convey something of our inner experience to others. The ways in which matter can be shaped for this purpose are myriad. Painting, sculpture, music, and narrative, are categories for artistic expression with a very ancient history. As our technological sophistication increases, more and more categories for artistic expression are added. But regardless of whether the medium is paint, photographic film, or electronic digital information the basic motivation for creative expression lies in our evolved psychology.